socialpolitical
Tuesday, October 7, 2014
open thread for paper-related matters
Something about the paper unclear to you? Have an idea you want to try out on others? Want to share something interesting you've learned? Frustrated and want to vent? Whatever it is, if it's paper-related, here's your opportunity...
Saturday, October 4, 2014
Belated question about Haidt
Haidt is worried about the level of acrimony in political debate. He voices his concerns throughout the book and uses a plea as the title of his final chapter: "Can't we all disagree more constructively?"
But he doesn't really put forward a positive case for why he's so anxious. He presents little data or evidence on why the current state of politics is such a cause for worry. Where is his evidence for why vigorous disagreement is so harmful?
Two thoughts:
But he doesn't really put forward a positive case for why he's so anxious. He presents little data or evidence on why the current state of politics is such a cause for worry. Where is his evidence for why vigorous disagreement is so harmful?
Two thoughts:
- The most I saw of an attempt of real analysis was in the last chapter, starting here: "... Many Americans feel that they're on a ship that's sinking, and the crew is too busy fighting with each other to bother plugging the leaks." And then he immediately presents the case of the difficulties of extending the debt ceiling in the summer of 2011.
- But the debt ceiling debate was crisis entirely self-made by the politicians. That ceiling is not a natural economic constraint, but a political one constructed by Congress. What's sinking Haidt's ship isn't say an iceberg, but the crew itself. If this is Haidt's best example, should we naturally defer more power to the hands of a group of people who have stirred up this trouble?
- If we indict the politicians in this case then we may ask how well they perform on average. If in general one views the acts of Congress as more mischievous than productive, then we can celebrate the lack of bipartisanship because we'll have fewer new statutes. We can ask whether a new law is on net worse for society than its absence; if it is worse, then Haidt's plea for less partisanship should be less welcome.
- Haidt might also contend with the rich history of partisanship and dissent doing good in America. Ill motivations may, in an invisible hand sort of way, make society better off. Our intuitions (the elephant) may lead us to seek out the worst ideas of the other side; on net there may be better discovery of truth if people are reflexively trying to prove the other side wrong. Consider that some of the best pieces of journalism have been motivated by a deep, fundamental disdain for power; the absence of that attitude may let more abuses to be covered up, and thus less pressure for change.
So what exactly is Haidt's case that partisanship is so bad?
Friday, September 19, 2014
open Haidt thread
This thread is for questions and thoughts about the material discussed by Haidt and by us in class. Somebody say something! I know you guys find this material interesting -- a lot of it is really fascinating. There's no reason for this discussion board to be so sterile. And discussion can only help you on the exams, both because it'll help you understand the material more, and because I may be moved to include material on the exams covered in these discussions.
Tuesday, September 16, 2014
Due dates for Humanity journal assignments.
The entry on Parts 1-2 is due midnight 10/3. Send it by attachment to the course email address, social.political.f14@gmail.com.
The other entries are each due on a two week schedule:
Part 3: 10/17
Part 4: 10/31
Part 5: 11/14
Parts 6-7: 11/28 (note: this is Thanksgiving)
If you have questions about this, or the assignment itself, you can put them in the comments section (unless it's urgent). Note that on the syllabus I didn't mention doing an entry on Parts 1 and 7, but then I realized I might as well incorporate them into the neighboring entry. The change is entirely a matter of giving you permission rather than a requirement -- you don't *have* to discuss Parts 1 and 7, but you *can* discuss them in the relevant entries, if you want to.
The other entries are each due on a two week schedule:
Part 3: 10/17
Part 4: 10/31
Part 5: 11/14
Parts 6-7: 11/28 (note: this is Thanksgiving)
If you have questions about this, or the assignment itself, you can put them in the comments section (unless it's urgent). Note that on the syllabus I didn't mention doing an entry on Parts 1 and 7, but then I realized I might as well incorporate them into the neighboring entry. The change is entirely a matter of giving you permission rather than a requirement -- you don't *have* to discuss Parts 1 and 7, but you *can* discuss them in the relevant entries, if you want to.
more about derivative and non-derivative attitudes
Here are a few thoughts about yesterday’s class and in anticipation of further inquiry.
Remember that the question we’re pursuing is: what
kinds of things to humans non-derivatively care about?
Again, to care about something derivatively is for
one's caring about it to manifest one's caring about something else. When
you derivatively care about something, in some sense the "real story"
behind your caring about it is that you care about something else.
This question is entirely psychological. It
isn’t normative or evaluative in any sense.
The question isn't (now) what humans *should* care about. Nor is
it the question what, given what we care about, we *should* do.
It's also entirely a question about contemporary
(or at least historical) human psychology. It isn't a question about
evolutionary history. I will say a bit more about this, following up on
my in-class comments.
The point can be a bit tricky because the question
of the evolutionary origins of an attitude and the question whether it is
derivative (and if so, of what) are both *explanatory* questions. But
they are *different* explanatory questions. One of them has to do with
whether there is some other attitude this attitude manifests -- that's the
question whether it's derivative. If so, then that other attitude will be
a psychological state contemporary with the attitude it explains. For
instance, your caring about your keys is explained by your caring about being
able to access your car or whatever. That's a fact about how one of your
current psychological states explains another current psychological state.
But of course evolutionary explanations aren't
like this. What evolution might give us is an explanation of why humans
tend to come to have attitudes like this (it would never give us anything like
a complete explanation of why you now have a certain attitude). These
evolutionary explanations will cite some fitness-enhancing effect of the
attitude. For instance, why do humans have lust? Presumably that attitude had a certain fitness-enhancing
effect in our ancestors who had it – it caused them to reproduce more, passing
on the genes responsible for their having it.
(Lust is such a good example for two reasons. First, it’s so obviously innate – we don’t
have to be trained to have it, although of course the details are to some
extent enculturable. Second, the
evolutionary explanation is, at least in large part, pretty obvious.)
So when we give evolutionary explanations we cite some effect of the trait we’re explaining. That’s true when the trait is an attitude; i.e., a state of caring about something. But it doesn’t follow that when we explain an attitude this way, the attitude in question is derivative of a state of caring about bringing about the relevant effect. Evolution doesn’t work by starting with our caring about the effect and then getting us to have attitudes which we take to promote the effect. Rather, it works by our acquiring attitudes which do in fact promote the effect, regardless of whether we’re even aware of that. Remember, the evolutionary process works on many traits aside from psychological states. For instance, it explains the traits of plants. The point is just that if we give an evolutionary explanation of a state of caring about X in terms of that state’s tending to have a certain effect – bringing about Y – that doesn’t mean that the state of caring about X is derivative (in our sense) of caring about Y. It doesn’t follow that we care about Y at all or even understand Y. In some sense the relevant effect is always the passing on of genes (at least in genetic evolution), but we didn’t even know about genes until recently.
A bit more trickily, perhaps, the question whether
an attitude is derivative of another attitude is not the question whether it is
developmentally promoted by that other attitude. For instance, suppose Jones realizes that he’d
be happier if he had more friends, and that he’ll have more friends if he cares
more about other people. So – from self-interested
motives – he cultivates more caring about other people. He may in fact succeed so that he comes to
care more about other people in themselves.
His egoistic concern is in part causally responsible for his
other-directed concern (“nepotistic” as I called it), but that doesn’t mean his
other-directed concern is just a manifestation of his self-directed
concern. It has taken on a life of its
own and become non-derivative.
To see the point, consider a simpler example. Suppose Jones is totally egoistic. Then he is given a pill which will affect his
brain in such a way that he will acquire some non-egoistic concern for
others. He has to decide whether to take
it. Of course, being totally egoistic,
if he takes it, then his later non-egoistic concern will be caused by his
egoistic decision to do so. But that
doesn’t mean it isn’t genuinely non-egoistic at the later time. People can change and genuinely acquire new
non-derivative concerns. In fact,
everyone does this. Think about someone
you now care about non-derivatively but whom you didn’t know a few years
ago. In the meantime you’ve come to have
new non-derivative attitudes, to this person.
Perhaps you originally met this person from self-interested motives –
you wanted to be happier and you thought meeting someone would help bring this
about say. But just because egoism is in
the causal history of your concern for this person it doesn’t follow that your
concern for them is egoistic in our sense.
Here’s one way of thinking about the difference
between the Jones-type case and the kind of case in which one’s concern for another
really is egoistic (e.g., is just using that person for sex, money, vanity, or
opportunities). The crucial point is
this: regarding certain attitudes, *part of what it is to have* the attitude is
to have dispositions to acquire other attitudes. In
particular, it is to have a disposition to acquire attitudes to things one
takes to be relevantly related to the object of the original attitude. For instance, to care about yourself in the
ordinary way *is* to be disposed to care about what you think will harm or
benefit you. Suppose Smith claims to
love Mary. And Smith realizes that Brown
is planning to assault Mary. Suppose
Smith simultaneously claims to love Mary but is utterly indifferent to Brown’s
plans. Can we make sense of this? It seems that Smith is being insincere in
saying he cares about Mary. Part of what
it is to care about someone is to be disposed to care about whether they’re
assaulted.
Now suppose that Smith really does care about
Mary. And suppose that when he comes to
learn about Brown’s plans, he isn’t indifferent – it matters to him, and he
wants to stop it or warn Mary or whatnot.
These latter attitudes are the manifestations of the dispositions which
constitute his caring about Mary. They
are thus derivative of his caring about Mary.
For instance, he has a desire to call the police. That desire is clearly derivative – he doesn’t
want to call them for its own sake. It’s
a manifestation of a disposition constitutive of his caring about Mary.
So we can give a more precise account of what it
is for an attitude to be derivative (and, correspondingly,
non-derivative). It isn’t just that it
is *caused by* another attitude. It
depends on how the causing occurs. If it
occurs in the way that Jones’ desire for his own happiness causes him to care about
others, or in the way that your desire for a relationship caused you to come to
care about a person you currently care about (in the above examples), then it
is not derivative. But if it is caused
in the sense that it merely manifests a disposition constitutive of another
attitude, then it is derivative.
Hmmm… I
intended to say more but didn’t think this would take up so much time and
space. Perhaps I’ll stop here. The more comments, the more inspired I’ll be
to write more. :-)
Questions?
Thoughts?
Tuesday, September 9, 2014
yourmorals.org
As he mentions in his book, Haidt is associated with a website which does research on moral psychology, called yourmorals.org. There are a lot of questionnaires at that site, helping us explore our moral intuitions and principles. A neat feature is that we can answer questionnaires as members of a group -- in our case, this class -- and it'll tally the results and give us a sense of the moral ideas of the members of our class. Of course, it's all anonymous, and also completely optional. But all you have to do is click on this link (opens in a new window), register, and then fill out the Moral Foundations Questionnaire, which is the first one. Again, it's totally anonymous, and the questions are interesting and fun. I also think it would be neat to do it again at the end of the class to see what has changed, and that'll have more validity if you do it both times. (If you already have an account at yourmorals, click on this link instead.) Let me know if you have any questions.
Btw, another reason to do it is that it'll help you get a better sense of Haidt's thinking about morality, as you need to for the first exam.
We can also use this blog post as a locus of discussion of the questions in the survey.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)